The Anti-Subjective Hypothesis: Michel Foucault and The Death of The Subject
The Anti-Subjective Hypothesis: Michel Foucault and The Death of The Subject
The Anti-Subjective Hypothesis: Michel Foucault and The Death of The Subject
AMY ALLEN
Let there be no misunderstanding: I do not claim that sex has not been prohibited or barred or
masked or misapprehended since the classical age. . . . I do not maintain that the prohibition of
sex is a ruse. . . . All these negative elements . . . which the repressive hypothesis groups together
in one great central mechanism destined to say no, are doubtless only component parts that have
a local and tactical role to play in a transformation into discourse, a technology of power, and a
will to knowledge that are far from being reducible to the former.2
In short, in Foucault’s view, there is much more to our alleged sexual repression
than initially meets the eye.
113
AMY ALLEN
In what follows, I will not be concerned with the repressive hypothesis per
se. Instead, I introduce this aspect of Foucault’s work because, just as Foucault
unmasks the repressive hypothesis, I intend to unmask and debunk an assump-
tion that has become commonplace in the critical literature on Foucault, an
assumption that I will term “the anti-subjective hypothesis.” The anti-subjective
hypothesis consists in the belief that the point of Foucault’s archaeological
analyses of discourse and his genealogical analyses of power/knowledge is to
attack, undermine, and eventually eradicate the concept of the human subject.
In short, those who subscribe to the anti-subjective hypothesis believe that
Foucault participates in, even celebrates, the so-called “death of the subject.”
This interpretation of Foucault has had an enormous impact on the reception of
Foucault in the United States, particularly by social and political philosophers.
Insofar as the capacity for being a thinking subject capable of reflecting on and
deliberating about courses of action seems to be a precondition for moral or
political agency, Foucault’s alleged eradication of the subject seems also to
commit him to a denial of the possibility of moral or political agency. Further-
more, insofar as moral agency is generally thought to be a precondition for
moral responsibility, Foucault’s participation in the death of the subject seems
to imply that it is no longer possible to make any claims regarding who is
responsible for unjust social and political arrangements. Indeed, all claims that
a set of social and political arrangements is unjust seem to be out the window as
well, since it is not clear that it makes sense any longer to speak of injustice in a
deterministic world such as Foucault’s is taken to be. Thus, the claim that
Foucault eradicates the subject is often the first step in an argument that serves
to justify a marginal place for Foucault in contemporary social and political
philosophy. Clearly, then, the stakes involved in this reading of Foucault are
quite high.
Interestingly enough, the anti-subjective hypothesis has been accepted by a
wide spectrum of commentators on Foucault, ranging from some of his harshest
critics to some of his most ardent supporters. While his critics bemoan the death
of the subject, his supporters applaud it. Given the virtual consensus among
commentators, one might be tempted to leave well enough alone. However, I
shall argue that a close analysis of the anti-subjective hypothesis and of the ar-
gument advanced in favor of it reveals that there is much more to Foucault’s
alleged eradication of the subject than initially meets the eye. After laying out
the argument that is advanced by supporters of this hypothesis, I shall argue that
this way of reading Foucault should be rejected. I shall suggest in its stead an
alternate interpretation of Foucault’s archaeologies and genealogies that reveals
his work to be an elaboration of the historically, culturally, and socially specific
conditions of possibility for subjectivity, rather than an eradication of this
114
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
115
AMY ALLEN
116
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
117
AMY ALLEN
One might think . . . that Foucault is heralding the death of the subject, that he is claiming that
the subject itself is only the result of the effects of power/knowledge regimes, that he completely
undermines and ridcules any and all talk of human agency. There is plenty of textual evidence to
support such claims. But it is also clear, especially in his late writings when he deals with the
question of the self’s relation to itself and the possibility of ‘the man who tries to invent himself’,
that he is not abandoning the idea that ‘we constitute ourselves as subjects acting on others’.14
In other words, Bernstein appeals to the late work on practices of the self as evi-
dence for the fact that Foucault must not have participated in the death of the
subject in his earlier work.
Foucault’s defenders acknowledge that Foucault’s untimely death in 1984
meant that he was unable to complete his project on practices of the self, but,
they claim, the seeds for an adequate account of subjectivity are still to be found
118
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
in his late works. This account of subjectivity, they maintain, can in turn provide
the necessary corrective for his earlier—admittedly overly deterministic—
accounts of the death of the subject.15 As Thomas Flynn puts it, the analysis in
the late Foucault “fills in a gap in ‘structuralist’ historiography, namely, the ab-
sence of the individual, responsible agent”;16 moreover, it does so without taking
on any of the baggage of the Cartesian, transcendental, and phenomenological
accounts of the subject that Foucault so vehemently criticized in his early work.
Unfortunately, this attempt to respond to the anti-subjective hypothesis does
not help matters much, since those who argue that Foucault’s archaeological and
genealogical works eradicate the subject tend to view his late turn to a study of
practices of the self as, at best, a capitulation to the arguments of his critics and,
at worst, an outright contradiction. Either way, many critics maintain, the turn to
an account of the subject in the late Foucault constitutes a radical and unrecon-
cilable break with his earlier projects.17 As such, it does not help to correct the
wholesale elimination of the subject that they diagnosed in his earlier work. Fur-
thermore, even if the late work could be reconciled with the early work, at least
one critic maintains that the result would not be an integrated and useful account
of the subject; on the contrary, Thomas McCarthy claims, we would merely be
left with an overly deterministic and holistic account cobbled together with an
overly voluntaristic and individualistic account. McCarthy writes:
[In Foucault’s early work,] everything was a function of context, of impersonal forces and fields,
from which there was no escape—the end of man. Now the focus is on ‘those intentional and
voluntary actions by which men not only set themselves rules of conduct but also seek to trans-
form themselves . . . and to make their life into an oeuvre’—with too little regard for social,
political, and economic context. Neither scheme provides an adequate framework for critical
social inquiry.18
Even taking the turn toward the self in the late Foucault into account, we are still
left without a coherent and viable account of subjectivity and, thus, without
workable conceptions of agency, responsibility, and resistance. If the reading I
have been discussing is correct, then the anti-subjective hypothesis still stands,
and Foucault’s view appears to remain in question.
In light of these compelling arguments in favor of the anti-subjective hypothe-
sis, and considering the unsavory implications of such an eradication of the sub-
ject, it appears that the most promising way to defend Foucault is to deny that he
was ever guilty in his archaeological and genealogical works of participating in
the death of the subject. I shall mount such a defense first by questioning one of
the key presuppositions of the argument in favor of the anti-subjective hypothe-
sis. I shall then proceed to offer an alternate reading of Foucault’s philosophical
project, one that takes seriously his own characterization of that project as “a
history of the different modes by which, in our culture, human beings are made
119
AMY ALLEN
120
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
point of these works is to shift subjectivity from the position of that which ex-
plains to the position of that which must be explained, from explanans to
explanandum.
One has to dispense with the constituent subject, to get rid of the subject itself, that’s to say, to
arrive at an analysis which can account for the constitution of the subject within a historical
framework. And this is what I would call genealogy, that is, a form of history which can account
for the constitution of knowledges, discourses, domains of objects, etc., without having to make
reference to a subject which is either transcendental in relation to the field of events or runs in its
empty sameness throughout the course of history.22
Now, this passage has been cited as evidence for the anti-subjective hypothesis
because in it Foucault claims that we have to “get rid of the subject itself.”23
However, I think that this kind of interpretation of this remark is misleading for
two reasons. First, Foucault initially says that what he wants to get rid of is the
“constituent subject,” or what I have called the subject as explanans. As I have
indicated, this seems a reasonable first step in the process of shifting the explan-
atory priority of the concept of subjectivity. Second, although Foucault goes on
to say that we have to “get rid of the subject itself,” the explicitly stated purpose
of doing so is to “arrive at an analysis which can account for the constitution of
121
AMY ALLEN
the subject within a historical framework.” In other words, Foucault’s aim is not
to get rid of the concept of subjectivity altogether; instead, he sets aside any con-
ception of the subject as constituent in order that he might better understand
how the subject is constituted in a particular way in this particular cultural and
historical milieu.
If we start with this kind of an understanding of Foucault’s philosophical proj-
ect, then we end up with a reading of his archaeological and genealogical works
that is very different from the one offered in support of the anti-subjective hy-
pothesis. Although a full account of all of the details of such a reading is beyond
the scope of this essay, I can offer the following sketch of it. Foucault’s archaeo-
logical works attempt to describe discourses without reference to foundational or
transcendental conceptions of the human subject. This does not mean that the
concept of subjectivity is irrelevant to this project; on the contrary, delineating
the ways in which historically specific discourses make possible particular
modes of subjectivity is precisely the point of that project. Thus, Foucault de-
scribes his project in The Archaeology of Knowledge as belonging “to that field
in which the questions of the human being, consciousness, origin, and the sub-
ject emerge, intersect, mingle, and separate off.”24 Similarly, in the preface to
the English edition of The Order of Things, Foucault emphasizes that although
his analysis starts at the level of discourses rather than at the level of individual
subjects or agents, this should not be taken as a denial of the possible efficacy of
any subject- or agent-centered account. On the contrary, he writes, “it is simply
that I wonder whether such descriptions are themselves enough, whether they do
justice to the immense density . . . of discourse.”25 Although he does argue
against the possibility of a particular sort of subject-centered dis-
course—namely, a humanist account which views the subject as founda-
tional—he makes it clear that his mode of investigation does not constitute “a
rejection of any other possible approach. Discourse in general . . . is so complex
a reality that we not only can, but should, approach it at different levels and with
different methods.”26 Here Foucault indicates that his aim is not to take the con-
cept of the subject out of philosophical investigation altogether; rather, his aim
is to turn philosophical investigation on the concept of subjectivity itself.
Furthermore, although Foucault’s investigation of discourse proceeds without
reference to a subject, the point of this investigation is to “grasp the subject’s
points of insertion, modes of functioning, and system of dependencies.”27 The
analysis addresses the following questions:
how, under what conditions, and in what forms can something like a subject appear in the order
of discourse? What place can it occupy in each type of discourse, what functions can it assume,
122
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
and by obeying what rules? In short, it is a matter of depriving the subject (or its substitute) of its
role as originator, and of analyzing the subject as a variable and complex function of discourse.28
Again, Foucault indicates here that the goal of his analysis is to resist the temp-
tation to explain discourse in terms of the constituent subject, and instead to
explain the subject as constituted through discourse, to shift the subject from the
explanans to the explanandum of philosophical inquiry. Such a shift allows
Foucault to examine the ways in which discursive practices constitute a histori-
cally, socially, and culturally specific, modern mode of subjectivity.
Although knowledge and discourse are the primary locus of Foucault’s early,
archaeological investigations, in his genealogical works, the locus shifts to in-
clude power alongside discourse as that which serves as a constitutive condition
for modern subjectivity. Perhaps the most striking aspect of Foucault’s analysis
of power is his rejection of the belief that power is solely or even primarily re-
pressive. Foucault insists that power could not possibly be effective if it only
functioned by saying “no.” As he writes, “if power were never anything but re-
pressive, if it never did anything but say no, do you really think one would be
brought to obey it?”29 His analysis of the repressive hypothesis, which I alluded
to above, illustrates this point. Far from being squelched by the repressive power
of moralistic, Victorian attitudes, discourses on sexuality and sexual practices in
our era have actually multiplied. Power does not function in the domain of sexu-
ality merely or even primarily by repressing, prohibiting, censuring, and restrict-
ing; it incites, produces, provokes, and induces; and it prohibits by producing
just as it produces by prohibiting.
For Foucault, as we have already seen, one of the key effects of power’s pro-
ductivity is the subject. However, Foucault’s investigations into the operation of
power are not attempts to write the subject out of philosophical analysis; once
again, they are inquiries into the conditions of possibility for modern subjectivity.
Thus, he characterizes his genealogies as attempts to demonstrate “how it is that
subjects are gradually, progressively, really and materially constituted through a
multiplicity of organisms, forces, energies, materials, desires, thoughts, etc. [His
genealogies] try to grasp subjection in its material instance as a constitution of
subjects.”30 Foucault’s account of disciplinary power in Discipline and Punish
illuminates this process. This account traces the process by which individuals are
subjected to normalizing disciplinary practices and thereby transformed into a
peculiarly modern kind of subject. Individuals are subject to disciplinary power,
which is exercised over them and subtly and insidiously constrains their choices,
desires, and actions, and, at the same time, they are made into subjects by disci-
plinary power, which creates various subject-positions and incites individuals to
take them up. In this way, power both enables the constitution of subjects and
constrains the subject so constituted. In and through its operation, power
123
AMY ALLEN
criticism is no longer going to be practiced in the search for formal structures with universal
value, but rather as a historical investigation into the events that have led us to constitute our-
selves and to recognize ourselves as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying. In that
sense, criticism is not transcendental . . .: it . . . seek[s] to treat the instances of discourse that
articulate what we think, say and do as so many historical events. And . . . it will not deduce
from the form of what we are what it is impossible for us to do and to know; but it will separate
out, from the contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer being,
doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think.31
124
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
125
AMY ALLEN
critics assume that Foucault, as a historian, makes claims about the human subject that must be
taken as objective in the crudest sense: that, for example, if Foucault assembles a genealogy ac-
cording to which subjectivity is a product of repressive self-forming technologies, then the
human being is nothing more than the product of those technologies. But very few historians,
even the most traditional, would understand the activity of writing history in this way; history
never says all there is to say.37
Here, in attempting to defuse the same sort of objection that I have been dis-
cussing, Moussa actually grants the objection but then suggests that it doesn’t
matter because Foucault, like any historian, had to pick and choose what to put
into and what to leave out of the construction of narrative. On this line of argu-
ment, we might say that it so happens that he chose (why? perhaps for reasons
of narrative consistency?) to put into his archaeologies and genealogies a lot of
stuff about discursive structures and power relations and nothing about the role
that individual subjects play in the construction of such structures, but that this
doesn’t necessarily mean that he thought that individuals did not play a role in
that construction.
I think that there may be something to what Moussa suggests, but I have two
worries about this strategy for responding to critics who accept the anti-
subjective hypothesis. The first is that this defense of Foucault does not really
meet the full force of the original objection, which is not just that Foucault
doesn’t talk enough about the concept of subjectivity but that his archaeologi-
cal and genealogical works seem to deny that this concept has any value at all,
to suggest that there is no such thing as subjectivity. I think that the reading
that I have proposed, which interprets Foucault’s archaeologies and genealo-
gies as offering historically and culturally specific conditions of possibility for
subjectivity, helps to explain why this isn’t the case. My second worry is that,
although I agree that Foucault was a very historically minded philosopher, he
was first and foremost a philosopher; analogously, I think that the reason he
brackets the concept of subjectivity in his archaeologies and genealogies is
first and foremost a philosophical rather than a historical one. The reading that
I have proposed also gives us a way to make sense of the philosophical ratio-
nale for this methodological move.
CONCLUSION
126
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
alternate reading of Foucault. First, for Foucault scholars, this way of reading
Foucault holds out the possibility of a new understanding of Foucault’s philo-
sophical project, one which emphasizes the continuity between the three periods
—archaeology, genealogy, and ethics—of his work. Now, the desire to find con-
tinuity in Foucault’s philosophical project may seem quite un-Foucaultian, but
recall that Foucault himself indicated toward the end of this life that he thought
there was such continuity to his work, and he claimed that the continuity could
be found in the fact that “it is not power, but the subject, which is the general
theme of my research.”38 The interpretation of Foucault that I have proposed al-
lows us to make sense of this remark, insofar as it allows us to see the point of
his archaeologies and genealogies as the elaboration of historically a priori con-
ditions of possibility for subjectivity, and his late work as a complementary—
rather than contradictory—account of the role that individuals play in their own
self-constitution.
A second implication of my argument is that it opens up new avenues of
thought with respect to several prominent debates that have surrounded
Foucault’s work in recent years, including the Foucault/Habermas debate and
the debate over the use and abuse of Foucault’s philosophy for feminist theory.
In each of these debates, Foucault’s alleged embrace of the death of the subject
and the implications thereof have been major stumbling blocks to an effective
exchange of ideas. If Foucault’s archaeological and genealogical works can be
read as an elaboration of the background conditions of possibility of subjectivity
rather than as a wholesale elimination of the subject itself, then the prospects for
a reconciliation between Foucault’s view of subjectivity and Habermas’s
intersubjective and dialectical account of individuation through socialization
seem much brighter.39 Although I would not dream of denying that significant
differences between Foucault’s and Habermas’s projects remain, a rapproche-
ment between Foucault and Habermas on the question of the intersubjective
constitution of subjectivity has the potential to reinvigorate the somewhat stag-
nant Foucault/Habermas debate. Foucault and Habermas have offered two of the
most subtle, interesting, and important philosophical analyses of society to be
produced in the latter half of the twentieth century, and yet, in my view, their
work has not been brought into serious and sustained dialogue. Similarly, the
reading of Foucault that I have proposed has the potential to advance the linger-
ing debate over the usefulness of Foucault’s work for feminist theory. Many
feminists, including Alcoff and Hartsock, have cited Foucault’s eradication of
the subject as a serious limitation of the usefulness of his work for feminist the-
ory. But as Nancy Fraser has suggested, “nothing in principle precludes that sub-
jects are both culturally constructed and capable of critique.”40 It is just that
feminists have yet to offer an account of subjectivity that emphasizes both the
way in which subjects are culturally constructed through relations of power and
127
AMY ALLEN
discourse and the critical capacities that subjects nonetheless (or, as a result)
have. I am not suggesting that the interpretation of Foucault I have offered here
provides, by itself, such an account; but I am suggesting that it provides a fruit-
ful starting point for the construction of such an account, since a greater rap-
prochement between poststructuralist accounts of the cultural construction of the
subject such as Foucault’s and critical-theoretical accounts of the capability of
subjects of critique such as Habermas’s seems like a particularly promising way
of arriving at such an account. The important point is that, on my reading of
Foucault, there is much less standing in the way of such a rapprochement than
has previously been thought.
Finally, the reading of Foucault that I have suggested here has the potential to
open up new ways of thinking about what we might call the structure/agency
problem in social and political philosophy. Philosophers and social and political
theorists have long struggled with the following paradox: on the one hand, if our
theories emphasize the autonomy, agency, and freedom of individuals, then they
run the risk of being blind to the massive impact that social, political, cultural,
and discursive structures have on the very formation of us as individuals; if, on
the other hand, our theories focus on such structures, then they run the risk of
painting an overly deterministic picture of the role that structures play in consti-
tuting individuals, thereby implicitly denying or at the very least undermining
the possibility of individual subjectivity, agency, and freedom. The challenge
that this paradox poses for philosophers is the necessity of finding a way of
thinking about the dialectical interrelationship between social, political, linguis-
tic, and cultural structures, on the one hand, and individual subjects/agents, on
the other. The reading of Foucault that I have suggested here makes it possible
to see his work as an especially productive starting point for a reconsideration of
this paradox because, on my account, far from coming down on the structure
side of this divide, Foucault’s work actually provides some of the theoretical and
conceptual resources necessary for working out the interrelationship between
structure and agency.
Dartmouth College
NOTES
An earlier version of this essay was presented at the Eastern Division Meeting of the American
Philosophical Association in Philadelphia; I am grateful to participants at that meeting for their ques-
tions and comments. Special thanks also to Linda Alcoff, Thomas McCarthy, and members of the
Department of Philosophy at Dartmouth College for their helpful suggestions on earlier versions of
this essay.
128
THE ANTI-SUBJECTIVE HYPOTHESIS
1 Michel Foucault, “The Minimalist Self,” in Michel Foucault: Politics, Philosophy, Culture, ed.
Lawrence D. Kritzman (New York: Routledge, 1988), 9.
2 Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, Vol. 1: An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley (New
York: Vintage, 1978), 12.
3 See Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans. Frederick G. Lawrence
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1987), chaps. 9, 10; Axel Honneth, The Critique of Power:
Reflective Stages in a Critical Social Theory, trans. Kenneth Baynes (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press, 1991), chaps. 4–6; Thomas McCarthy, “The Critique of Impure Reason: Foucault and the
Frankfurt School,” in McCarthy, Ideals and Illusions: On Deconstruction and Reconstruction
in Contemporary Critical Theory (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991); Michael Walzer, “The
Politics of Michel Foucault,” in Foucault: A Critical Reader, ed. David Hoy (Oxford: Blackwell,
1986); Charles Taylor, “Foucault on Freedom and Truth,” in Foucault, ed. Hoy; Nancy Hartsock,
“Foucault on Power: A Theory for Women?” in Feminism/Postmodernism, ed. Linda Nicholson
(New York: Routledge, 1990); and Linda Alcoff, “Feminist Politics and Foucault: The Limits to
a Collaboration,” in Crises in Continental Philosophy, ed. Arlene Dallery and Charles Scott
(Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1990).
4 Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences (New York: Vintage,
1970), 387.
5 Honneth, Critique of Power, 112.
6 McCarthy, “The Critique of Impure Reason,” 59.
7 Alcoff, “Feminist Politics and Foucault,” 71.
8 On this point, see McCarthy, “The Critique of Impure Reason,” 56–58, and Honneth, Critique of
Power, chaps. 4–6.
9 For example, see Foucault, “Power and Sex,” in Politics, Philosophy, Culture, 122.
10 Alcoff, “Feminist Politics and Foucault,” 76.
11 Hartsock, “Foucault on Power,” 163.
12 On this point, see also William Connolly, “Taylor, Foucault, and Otherness,” Political Theory,
13 (1985): 365–76.
13 Foucault is not claiming here that the subject literally invents itself (for clearly this would pre-
suppose a subject who is doing the inventing); instead, he claims that the subject defines itself in
terms of “patterns that he finds in his culture and which are proposed, suggested and imposed on
him by his culture, his society, and his social group.” Foucault, “The Ethic of Care for the Self as
a Practice of Freedom,” in The Final Foucault, ed. James Bernauer and David Rasmussen (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988), 11. On this point, see James Johnson, “Communication, Criti-
cism, and the Postmodern Consensus: An Unfashionable Interpretation of Michel Foucault,”
Political Theory, 25 (1997): 578, n. 20.
14 Richard Bernstein, The New Constellation: The Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity/
Postmodernity (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992), 154.
15 For variations of this argument, see Jana Sawicki, “Foucault, Feminism, and Questions of Iden-
tity,” in The Cambridge Companion to Foucault, ed. Gary Gutting (Cambridge, U.K.: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1994); Thomas Flynn, “Truth and Subjectivation in the Later Foucault,”
Journal of Philosophy, 82 (1985): 531–40; and Lois McNay, Foucault and Feminism: Power,
Gender, and the Self (Boston: Northeastern University Press, 1992).
16 Flynn, “Truth and Subjectivation in the Later Foucault,” 538.
17 For this argument, see Peter Dews, “The Return of the Subject in Late Foucault,” Radical Philos-
ophy, 51 (1989): 37–41. Bernstein acknowledges this problem as well, when he notes that
Foucault’s notion of ethics “presupposes the notion of an ethical or moral agent that can be free
and that can ‘master’ itself. But Foucault not only fails to explicate this sense of agency, his
129
AMY ALLEN
genealogical analyses seem effectively to undermine any talk of agency which is not a precipitate
of power/knowledge regimes” (Bernstein, The New Constellation, 164).
18 McCarthy, “The Critique of Impure Reason,” 74.
19 Foucault, “Afterword: The Subject and Power,” in Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and
Hermeneutics, ed. Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, 2nd ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1983), 208.
20 Ibid., 209.
21 Foucault, “Two Lectures,” in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–
1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon, 1980), 98.
22 Foucault, “Truth and Power,” in Power/Knowledge, 117.
23 See, for example, Alcoff’s reading of this passage in “Feminist Politics and Foucault,” 71.
24 Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Sheridan Smith (New York: Pan-
theon, 1972), 16.
25 Foucault, The Order of Things, xiii.
26 Ibid., xiv, emphasis added.
27 Michel Foucault, “What Is an Author?” in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York:
Pantheon, 1984), 118.
28 Ibid. See also Foucault, The Order of Things, xiv.
29 Foucault, “Truth and Power,” in Power/Knowledge, 119.
30 Foucault, “Two Lectures,” in Power/Knowledge, 97.
31 Foucault, “What Is Enlightenment?” in The Foucault Reader, 45–46.
32 See Foucault, The Order of Things, for a discussion of the historical a priori.
33 By making the argument that Foucault’s work contains a conception of human subjectivity—
indeed, that the conception of the constituted subject is the focus of Foucault’s work—I do not
mean to argue that this conception is a fully adequate one. In fact, I think it is not. In my view,
even in his late work, Foucault does not give a fully adequate account of the capacity of the
subject for critical agency. Such an account has been offered by Jürgen Habermas. Up to now,
however, the acceptance of the anti-subjective hypothesis has been a major stumbling block to an
effective exchange between Foucaultians and Habermasians; my hope is that debunking the
anti-subjective hypothesis can serve as a necessary first step on the road to a more fruitful
rapprochement between these two positions.
34 Ian Hacking, “Self-Improvement,” in Foucault, ed. Hoy, 238.
35 Foucault, “What Is Enlightenment?” in The Foucault Reader, 42.
36 Derrida makes a similar sort of claim about Foucault in an interview with Jean-Luc Nancy: “we
would appear to have a history of subjectivity that, in spite of certain massive declarations of the
effacement of the figure of man, certainly never consisted in ‘liquidating’ the Subject” (quoted in
Peter Dews, “The Truth of the Subject,” in Deconstructive Subjectivities, ed. Peter Dews and
Simon Critchley (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1996), 149.)
37 Mario Moussa, “Foucault and the Problem of Agency: Or, Toward a Practical Philosophy,” in
Ethics and Danger: Essays on Heidegger and Continental Thought, ed. Arleen Dallery and
Charles Scott (Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press, 1992).
38 Foucault, “Afterword,” in Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, ed. Hubert
Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, 209.
39 For this account, see Jürgen Habermas, “Individuation through Socialization: On George Herbert
Mead’s Theory of Subjectivity,” in Habermas, Postmetaphysical Thinking, trans. William Mark
Hohengarten (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1992).
40 Nancy Fraser, “False Antitheses: A Response to Seyla Benhabib and Judith Butler,” in Seyla
Benhabib, Judith Butler, Drucilla Cornell, and Nancy Fraser, Feminist Contentions: A Philo-
sophical Exchange, ed. Linda Nicholson (New York: Routledge, 1995), 67.
130